Gestalt theory, Max Wertheimer (1924)
Über Gestalttheorie [an address before the Kant Society, Berlin, '7th December, 1924], Erlangen, 1925.
In the translation by Willis D. Ellis published in his "Source Book of Gestalt Psychology,"
New York: Harcourt, Brace and Co, 1938.
What is Gestalt theory and what does it intend? Gestalt theory was the outcome
of concrete investigations in psychology, logic, and epistemology. The prevailing
situation at the time of its origin may be briefly sketched as follows. We go from
the world of everyday events to that of science, and not unnaturally assume that
in making this transition we shall gain a deeper and more precise understanding
of essentials. The transition should mark an advance. And yet, though one may have
learned a great deal, one is poorer than before. It is the same in psychology. Here
too we find science intent upon a systematic collection of data, yet often excluding
through that very activity precisely that which is most vivid and real in the living
phenomena it studies. Somehow the thing that matters has eluded us.
What happens when a problem is solved, when one suddenly "sees the point"?
Common as this experience is, we seek in vain for it in the textbooks of psychology.
Of things arid, poor, and inessential there is an abundance, but that which really
matters is missing. Instead we are told of formation of concepts, of abstraction
and generalization, of class concepts and judgments, perhaps of associations, creative
phantasy, intuitions, talents - anything but an answer to our original problem.
And what are these last words but names for the problem? Where are the penetrating
answers? Psychology is replete with terms of great potentiality - personality, essence,
intuition, and the rest. But when one seeks to grasp their concrete content, such
terms fail.
This is the situation and it is characteristic of modern science that the same
problem should appear everywhere. Several attempts have been made to remedy the
matter. One was a frank defeatism preaching the severance of science and life: there
are regions which are inaccessible to science. Other theories established a sharp
distinction between the natural and moral sciences: the exactitude and precision
of chemistry and physics are characteristic of natural science, but "scientific"
accuracy has no place in a study of the mind and its ways. This must be renounced
in favour of other categories.
Without pausing for further examples, let us consider rather a question naturally
underlying the whole discussion: Is "science" really the kind of thing
we have implied? The word science has often suggested a certain outlook, certain
fundamental assumptions, certain procedures and attitudes - but do these imply that
this is the only possibility of scientific method? Perhaps science already embodies
methods leading in an entirely different direction, methods which have been continually
stifled by the seemingly necessary, dominant ones. It is conceivable, for instance,
that a host of facts and problems have been concealed rather than illuminated by
the prevailing scientific tradition. Even though the traditional methods of science
are undoubtedly adequate in many cases, there may be others where they lead us astray.
Perhaps something in the very nature of the traditional outlook may have led its
exponents at times to ignore precisely that which is truly essential.
Gestalt theory will not be satisfied with sham solutions suggested by a simple
dichotomy of science and life. Instead, Gestalt theory is resolved to penetrate
the problem itself by examining the fundamental assumptions of science. It has long
seemed obvious - and is, in fact, the characteristic tone of European science -
that "science" means breaking up complexes into their component elements.
Isolate the elements, discover their laws, then reassemble them, and the problem
is solved. All wholes are reduced to pieces and piecewise relations between pieces.
The fundamental "formula" of Gestalt theory might be expressed in this
way [1]. There are wholes, the behaviour of which
is not determined by that of their individual elements, but where the part-processes
are themselves determined by the intrinsic nature of the whole. It is the hope of
Gestalt theory to determine the nature of such wholes.
With a formula such as this one might close, for Gestalt theory is neither more
nor less than this. It is not interested in puzzling out philosophic questions which
such a formula might suggest.
Gestalt theory has to do with concrete research; it is not only an outcome but
a device : not only a theory about results but a means toward further discoveries.
This is not merely the proposal of one or more problems but an attempt to see what
is really taking place in science. This problem cannot be solved by listing possibilities
for systematization, classification, and arrangement. If it is to be attacked at
all, we must be guided by the spirit of the new method and by the concrete nature
of the things themselves which we are studying, and set ourselves to penetrate to
that which is really given by nature.
There is another difficulty that may be illustrated by the following example.
Suppose a mathematician shows you a proposition and you begin to "classify"
it. This proposition, you say, is of such and such type, belongs in this or that
historical category, and so on. Is that how the mathematician works?
"Why, you haven't grasped the thing at all," the mathematician will
exclaim. "See here, this formula is not an independent, closed fact that can
be dealt with for itself alone. You must see its dynamic functional relationship
to the whole from which it was lifted or you will never understand it."
What holds for the mathematical formula applies also to the "formula"
of Gestalt theory. The attempt of Gestalt theory to disclose the functional meaning
of its own formula is no less strict than is the mathematician's. The attempt to
explain Gestalt theory in a short essay is the more difficult because of the terms
which are used: part, whole, intrinsic determination. All of them have in the past
been the topic of endless discussions where each disputant has understood them differently.
And even worse has been the cataloguing attitude adopted toward them. What they
lacked has been actual research. Like many another "philosophic" problem
they have been withheld from contact with reality and scientific work.
About all I can hope for in so short a discussion is to suggest a few of the
problems which at present occupy the attention of Gestalt theory and something of
the way they are being attacked.
To repeat: the problem has not merely to do with scientific work - it is a fundamental
problem of our times. Gestalt theory is not something suddenly and unexpectedly
dropped upon us from above; it is, rather, a palpable convergence of problems ranging
throughout the sciences and the various philosophic standpoints of modern times.
Let us take, for example, an event in the history of psychology.
One turned from a living experience to science and asked what it had to say about
this experience, and one found an assortment of elements, sensational images, feelings,
acts of will and laws governing these elements - and was told, "Take your choice,
reconstruct from them the experience you had." Such procedure led to difficulties
in concrete psychological research and to the emergence of problems which defied
solution by traditional analytic methods. Historically the most important impulse
came from v. Ehrenfels who raised the following problem. Psychology had said that
experience is a compound of elements: we hear a melody and then, upon hearing it
again, memory enables us to recognize it. But what is it that enables us to recognize
the melody when it is played in a new key? The sum of the elements is different,
yet the melody is the same; indeed, one is often not even aware that a transposition
has been made.
When in retrospect we consider the prevailing situation we are struck by two
aspects of v. Ehrenfels's thesis; on the one hand one is surprised at the essentially
summative character of his theory, on the other one admires his courage in propounding
and defending his proposition. Strictlv interpreted, v. Ehrenfels's position was
this: I play a familiar melody of six tones and employ six new tones, yet you recognize
the melody despite the change. There must be a something more than the sum of six
tones, viz. a seventh something, which is the form-quality, the Gestaltqualität,
of the original six. It is this seventh factor or element which enabled you to recognize
the melody despite its transposition.
However strange this view may seem, it shares with many another subsequently abandoned
hypothesis the honour of having clearly seen and emphasized a fundamental problem.
But other explanations were also proposed. One maintained that in addition to the
six tones there were intervals - relations - and that these were what remained constant.
In other words we are asked to assume not only elements but "relations-between-elements"
as additional components of the total complex. But this view failed to account for
the phenomenon because in some cases the relations too may be altered without destroying
the original melody.
Another type of explanation, also designed to bolster the elementaristic hypothesis,
was that to this total of six or more tones there come certain "higher processes"
which operate upon the given material to "produce" unity. [2]
This was the situation until Gestalt theory raised the radical question: Is it
really true that when I hear a melody I have a sum of individual tones (pieces)
which constitute the primary foundation of my experience? Is not perhaps the reverse
of this true? What I really have, what I hear of each individual note, what I experience
at each place in the melody is apart which is itself determined by the character
of the whole. What is given me by the melody does not arise (through the agency
of any auxiliary factor) as a secondary process from the sum of the pieces as such.
Instead, what takes place in each single part already depends upon what the whole
is. The flesh and blood of a tone depends from the start upon its role in the melody:
a b as leading tone to c is something radically different from the b as tonic. It
belongs to the flesh and blood of the things given in experience [Gegebenheiten],
how, in what role, in what function they are in their whole.
Let us leave the melody example and turn to another field. Take the case of threshold
phenomena. It has long been held that a certain stimulus necessarily produces a
certain sensation. Thus, when two stimuli are sufficiently different, the sensations
also will be different. Psychology is filled with careful inquiries regarding threshold
phenomena. To account for the difficulties constantly being encountered it was assumed
that these phenomena must be influenced by higher mental functions, judgments, illusions,
attention, etc. And this continued until the radical question was raised : Is it
really true that a specific stimulus always gives rise to the same sensation? Perhaps
the prevailing. whole-conditions will themselves determine the effect of stimulation?
This kind of formulation leads to experimentation, and experiments show, for example,
that when I see two colours the sensations I have are determined by the whole-conditions
of the entire stimulus situation. Thus, also, the same local physical stimulus pattern
can give rise to either a unitary and homogeneous figure, or to an articulated figure
with different parts, all depending upon the whole-conditions which may favour either
unity or articulation. Obviously the task, then, is to investigate these "whole-conditions"
and discover what influences they exert upon experience.
Advancing another step we come to the question whether perhaps any part depends
upon the particular whole in which it occurs. Experiments, largely on vision, have
answered this question in the affirmative. Among other things they demand that the
traditional theory of visual contrast be replaced by a theory which takes account
of whole-part conditions. [3]
Our next point is that my field comprises also my Ego. There is not from the
beginning an Ego over-against others, but the genesis of an Ego offers one of the
most fascinating problems, the solution of which seems to lie in Gestalt principles.
However, once constituted, the Ego is a functional part of the total field. Proceeding
as before we may therefore ask: What happens to the Ego as a part of the field?
Is the resulting behaviour the piecewise sort of thing associationism, experience
theory, and the like, would have us believe? Experimental results contradict this
interpretation and again we often find that the laws of whole-processes operative
in such a field tend toward a "meaningful" behaviour of its parts.
This field is not a summation of sense data and no description of it which considers
such separate pieces to be primary will be correct. If it were, then for children,
primitive peoples and animals experience would be nothing but piece-sensations.
The next most developed creatures would have, in addition to independent sensations,
something higher, and so on. But this whole picture is the opposite of what actual
inquiry has disclosed. We have learned to recognize the "sensations" of
our textbooks as products of a late culture utterly different from the experiences
of more primitive stages. Who experiences the sensation of a specific red in that
sense? What the man of the streets, children, or primitive men normally react to
is something coloured but at the same time exciting, gay, strong, or affecting -
not "sensations".
The programme to treat the organism as a part in a larger field necessitates
the reformulation of the problem as to the relation between organism and environment.
The stimulus-sensation connection must be replaced by a connection between alteration
in the field conditions, the vital situation, and the total reaction of the organism
by a change in its attitude, striving, and feeling.
There is, however, another step to be considered. A man is not only a part of
his field, he is also one among other men. When a group of people work together
it rarely occurs, and then only under very special conditions, that they constitute
a mere-sum of independent Egos. Instead the common enterprise often becomes their
mutual concern and each works as a meaningfully functioning part of the whole. Consider
a group of South Sea Islanders engaged in some community occupation, or a group
of children playing together. Only under very special circumstances does an "I"
stand out alone. Then the balance which obtained during harmonious and systematic
occupation may be upset and give way to a surrogate (under certain conditions, pathological)
new balance. [4]
Further discussion of this point would carry us into the work of social and cultural
science which cannot be followed here. Instead let us consider certain other illustrations.
What was said above of stimulus and sensation is applicable to physiology and the
biological sciences no less than to psychology. It has been tried, for example,
by postulating sums of more and more special apparatus, to account for meaningful
or, as it is often called, purposive behaviour. Once more we find meaninglessly
combined reflexes taken for granted although it is probable that even with minute
organisms it is not true that a piece-stimulus automatically bring about its corresponding
piece-effect.
Opposing this view is vitalism which, however, as it appears to Gestalt theory,
also errs in its efforts to solve the problem, for it, too, begins with the assumption
that natural occurrences are themselves essentially blind and haphazard - and adds
a mystical something over and above them which imposes order. Vitalism fails to
inquire of physical events whether a genuine order might not already prevail amongst
them. And yet nature does exhibit numerous instances of physical wholes in which
part events are determined by the inner structure of the whole. [5]
These brief references to biology will suffice to remind us that whole-phenomena
are not "merely" psychological, but appear in other sciences as well.
Obviously, therefore, the problem is not solved by separating off various provinces
of science and classifying whole-phenomena as something peculiar to psychology.
The fundamental question can be very simply stated: Are the parts of a given
whole determined by the inner structure of that whole, or are the events such that,
as independent, piecemeal, fortuitous and blind the total activity is a sum of the
part-activities? Human beings can, of course, devise a kind of physics of their
own - e.g. a sequence of machines - exemplifying the latter half of our question,
but this does not signify that all natural phenomena are of this type. Here is a
place where Gestalt theory is least easily understood and this because of the great
number of prejudices about nature which have accumulated during the centuries. Nature
is thought of as something essentially blind in its laws, where whatever takes place
in the whole is purely a sum of individual occurrences. This view was the natural
result of the struggle which physics has always had to purge itself of teleology.
To-day it can be seen that we are obliged to traverse other routes than those suggested
by this kind of purposivism.
Let us proceed another step and ask: How does all this stand with regard to the
problem of body and mind? What does my knowledge of another's mental experiences
amount to and how do I obtain it? There are, of course, old and established dogmas
on these points: The mental and physical are wholly heterogeneous: There obtains
between them an absolute dichotomy. (From this point of departure philosophers have
drawn an array of metaphysical deductions so as to attribute all the good qualities
to mind while reserving for nature the odious.) As regards the second question,
my discerning mental phenomena in others is traditionally explained as inference
by analogy. Strictly interpreted the principle here is that something mental is
meaninglessly coupled with something physical. I observe the physical and infer
the mental from it more or less according to the following scheme: I see someone
press a button on the wall and infer that he wants the light to go on. There may
be couplings of this sort. However, many scientists have been disturbed by this
dualism.and have tried to save themselves by recourse to very curious hypotheses.
Indeed, the ordinary person would violently refuse to believe that when he sees
his companion startled, frightened, or angry he is seeing only certain physical
occurrences which themselves have nothing to do (in their inner nature) with the
mental, being only superficially coupled with it: you have frequently seen this
and this combined ... etc. There have been many attempts to surmount this problem.
One speaks, for example, of intuition and says there can be no other possibility,
for I see my companion's fear. It is not true, argue the intuitionists, that I see
only the bare bodily activities meaninglessly coupled with other and invisible activities.
However inadmissible it may otherwise be, an intuition theory does have at least
this in its favour, it shows a suspicion that the traditional procedure might be
successfully reversed. But the word intuition is at best only a naming of that which
we must strive to lay hold of.
This and other hypotheses, apprehended as they now are, will not advance scientific
pursuit, for science demands fruitful penetration, not mere cataloguing and systematization.
But the question is, How does the matter really stand? Looking more closely we find
a I third assumption, namely that a process such as fear is a matter of consciousness.
Is this true? Suppose you see a person who is kindly or benevolent. Does anyone
suppose that this person is feeling mawkish? No one could possibly believe that.
The characteristic feature of such behaviour has very little to do with consciousness.
It has been one of the easiest contrivances of philosophy to identify a man's real
behaviour and the direction of his mind with his consciousness. Parenthetically,
in the opinion of many people the distinction between idealism and materialism implies
that between the noble and the ignoble. Yet does one really mean by this to contrast
consciousness with the blithesome budding of trees? Indeed, what is there so repugnant
about the materialistic and mechanical? What is so attractive about the idealistic?
Does it come from the material qualities of the connected pieces? Broadly speaking
most psychological theories and textbooks, despite their continued emphasis upon
consciousness, are far more "materialistic", arid, and spiritless than
a living tree - which probably has no consciousness at all. The point is not what
the material pieces are, but what kind of whole it is. Proceeding in terms of specific
problems one soon realizes how many bodily activities there are which give no hint
of a separation between body and mind. Imagine a dance, a dance full of grace and
joy. What is the situation in such a dance? Do we have a summation of physical limb
movements and a psychical consciousness? No. Obviously this answer does not solve
the problem; we have to start anew - and it seems to me that a proper and fruitful
point of attack has been discovered. [6] One finds
many processes which, in their dynamical form, are identical regardless of variations
in the material character of their elements. When a man is timid, afraid or energetic,
happy or sad, it can often be shown that the course of his physical processes is
Gestalt-identical with the course pursued by the mental processes.
Again In I can only indicate the direction of thought. I have touched on the
question of body and mind merely to show that the problem we are discussing also
has its philosophic aspects. To strengthen the import of the foregoing suggestions
let us consider the fields of epistemology and logic. For centuries the assumption
has prevailed that our world is essentially a summation of elements. For Hume and
largely also for Kant the world is like a bundle of fragments, and the dogma of
meaningless summations continues to play its part. As for logic, it supplies: concepts,
which when rigorously viewed are but sums of properties; classes, which upon closer
inspection prove to be mere catchalls ; syllogisms, devised by arbitrarily lumping
together any two propositions having the character that ... etc. When one considers
what a concept is in living thought, what it really means to grasp a conclusion;
when one considers what the crucial thing is about a mathematical proof and the
concrete interrelationships it involves, one sees that the categories of traditional
logic have accomplished nothing in this direction. [7]
It is our task to inquire, whether a logic is possible which is not piecemeal.
Indeed the same question arises in mathematics also. Is it necessary that all mathematics
be established upon a piecewise basis? What sort of mathematical system would it
be in which this were not the case? There have been attempts to answer the latter
question but almost always they have fallen back in the end upon the old procedures.
This fate has overtaken many, for the result of training in piecewise thinking is
extraordinarily tenacious. It is not enough and certainly does not constitute a
solution of the, principal problem if one shows that the atoms a of mathematics
are both piecemeal and t the same time evince something of the opposite character.
The problem has been scientifically grasped only when an attack specifically designed
to yield positive results has been launched. Just how this attack is to be made
seems to many mathematicians a colossal problem, but perhaps the quantum theory
will force the mathematicians to attack it.
This brings us to the close of an attempt to present a view of the problem as
illustrated by its specific appearances in various fields. In concluding I may suggest
a certain unification of these illustrations somewhat as follows. I consider the
situation from the point of view of a theory of aggregates and say: How should a
world be where science, concepts, inquiry, investigation, and comprehension of inner
unities were impossible? The answer is obvious. This world would be a manifold of
disparate pieces. Secondly, what kind of world would there have to be in which a
piecewise science would apply? The answer is again quite simple, for here one needs
only a system of recurrent couplings that are blind and piecewise in character,
whereupon everything is available for a pursuit of the traditional piecewise methods
of logic, mathematics, and science generally in so far as these presuppose this
kind of world. But there is a third kind of aggregate which has been but cursorily
investigated. These are the aggregates in which a manifold is not compounded from
adjacently situated pieces but rather such that a term at its place in that aggregate
is determined by the whole-laws of the aggregate itself.
Pictorially: suppose the world were a vast plateau upon which were many musicians.
I walk about listening and watching the players. First suppose that the world is
a meaningless plurality. Everyone does as he will, each for himself. What happens
together when I hear ten players might be the basis for my guessing as to what they
all are doing, but this is merely a matter of chance and probability much as in
the kinetics of gas molecules. - A second possibility would be that each time one
musician played c, another played f so and so many seconds later. I work out a theory
of blind couplings but the playing as a whole remains meaningless. This is what
many people think physics does, but the real work of physics belies this. - The
third possibility is, say, a Beethoven symphony where it would be possible for one
to select one part of the whole and work from that towards an idea of the structural
principle motivating and determining the whole. Here the fundamental laws are not
those of fortuitous pieces, but concern the very character of the event.
Footnotes:
[1] "Man könnte das Grundproblem der Gestalttheorie etwa so zu formulieren suchen: Es gibt Zusammenhänge, bei denen nicht, was im Ganzen geschieht, sich daraus herleitet, wie die einzelnen Stücke sind und sich zusammensetzen, sondern umgekehrt, wo - im prägnanten Fall - sich das, was an einem Teil dieses Ganzen geschieht, bestimmt von inneren Strukturgesetzen dieses seines Ganzen." [-> back to text]
[2] Compare KOFFKA, K. (1938). Reply to v. Benussi. In: W. D. Ellis (Ed.), A Source Book of Gestalt Psychology, 371-378. Reprint (1997): New York: The Gestalt Journal Press. [-> back to text]
[3] See BENARY, W. (1938). The Influence of form on Brightness Contrast. In: W. D. Ellis (Ed.), A Source Book of Gestalt Psychology, 104-108. Reprint (1997): New York: The Gestalt Journal Press. [-> back to text]
[4] The suggestions given in this paragraph have been worked out in further detail by SCHULTE, H. (1938). An Approach to a Gestalt Theory of Paranoic Phenomena. In: W. D. Ellis (Ed.), A Source Book of Gestalt Psychology, 362-369. Reprint (1997): New York: The Gestalt Journal Press. [-> back to text]>
[5] See KÖHLER, W. (1938). Physical Gestalten. In: W. D. Ellis (Ed.), A Source Book of Gestalt Psychology, 17-54. Reprint (1997): New York: The Gestalt Journal Press. [-> back to text]
[6] Compare HORNBOSTEL; E. M. v. (1938). The Unity of the Senses. In: W. D. Ellis (Ed.), A Source Book of Gestalt Psychology, 210-216. Reprint (1997): New York: The Gestalt Journal Press. [-> back to text]
[7] Compare in this connection WERTHEIMER, M. (1938). The Syllogism and Productive Thinking. In: W. D. Ellis (Ed.), A Source Book of Gestalt Psychology, 274-282. Reprint (1997): New York: The Gestalt Journal Press. [-> back to text]